Nyaya-Vaisheshika categories (Study)
by Diptimani Goswami | 2014 | 61,072 words
This page relates ‘Historical Survey of Nyaya System� of the study on the Nyaya-Vaisheshika categories with special reference to the Tarkasangraha by Annambhatta. Both Nyaya and Vaisesika are schools of ancient Indian Philosophy, and accepted in their system various padarthas or objects of valid knowledge. This study investigates how the Tarkasamgraha reflects these categories in the combined Nyayavaisesika school.
Go directly to: Footnotes.
Historical Survey of ⲹ System
The ⲹ System is one of the six orthodox systems of Indian Philosophy. The oldest name of ⲹ is Ānvikṣikī. Ānvikṣikī means the science of inquiry. It comprises Āٳ- and the theory of reasons. Manu has used the term Ānvikṣikī to mean Āٳ and his followers also called ĀԱīṣiī as a branch of the Vedas.[1] ṭiⲹ has accepted ĀԱīṣiī as a separate branch of study over and above, Trayi (the Vedas), ٳ (commerce) and ٲṇḍīپ (polity).[2] ṭiⲹ has included the ṃkⲹ, Yoga and ǰⲹٲ in the Ānvikṣikī.[3] The time of the formation of Ānvikṣikī as a distinct branch of learning was about 650 B.C.[4] ĀԱīṣiī was called ٳ-śٰ or Hetu վ as it dealt predominantly with the science of reasoning. This meaning of ĀԱīṣiī is found in the ѲԳܲṃh[5], Ѳٲ[6] etc. It is also known as ղ첹, the art of debate or 岹-, the art of discussion. In later times Ānvikṣikī has come to be denoted as ⲹ-śٰ (the science of true reasoning).
The authorship of ĀԱīṣiī is ascribed to Gotama or Gautama. It is stated in the ñⲹṛt that ⲹ is included in the fourteen principal branches of learning.[7] In the Ѳٲⲹ-ʳܰṇa it is pointed out that ⲹ vidyā along with the Vedas, proceed from the mouth of .[8] Many tenets of ⲹ are found in the ŚԳپ-parva of the Ѳٲ.[9]
However, there were many teachers who propounded ⲹ philosophy. It is said in the Ā徱貹 of the Ѳٲ that there were a number of sages in the hermitage of śⲹ貹 who knew true meanings of demonstration, refutation and conclusion.[10] These sages were the early teachers of the ⲹ-śٰ. But nothing is known about these early teachers.
The ⲹ system, formulated by Gautama, is also known as ṣa岹 ٲśԲ because another name of Gautama is ṣa岹. Mādhavācārya designates the ⲹ system as ṣa岹 system in his 岹śԲṃg. The ⲹ system is atomistic, pluralistic and realistic. The meaning of the term ⲹ is right or justice.[11] Etymologically this word means ‘that by which man is guided� (nīyate aneneti Բⲹ�). �ⲹśٰ is therefore the science of right judgement or true reasoning�[12]
Vatsyāyana defines ⲹ as an examination of objects by evidences.[13] He also points Out that the distinctive characteristic of ⲹ is its critical treatment of metaphysical problems. 峦貹پ points out that ⲹ signifies the critical examination of the objects of knowledge by means of the canons of logical proof.[14]
“T word ⲹ derived from the root � ni is sometimes explained as that by which sentences and words could be interpreted as having one particular meaning and not another and on the strength of this even Vedic accents of words (which indicate the meaning of compound words by pointing out the particular kind of compound in which the words entered into combination) were called ⲹ.�[15] Another name of ⲹ system is ʰṇaśٰ because in this we find discussion in details regarding ṇa. The valid knowledge is called and the means by which this is achieved is known as ṇa. ٲⲹԲ states in his work that ṇa is the tool of knowledge.[16] Uddyotakara defines ṇa as the �ܱ貹ٳ�� cause of knowledge.[17] He also argues that this definition may be said to be over-pervasive since the cogniser and the object cognized are also known as the cause of knowledge. He rejects this argument by saying that it is the ṇa by which the cogniser and the object cognized are known and hence ṇa is regarded as the real cause of knowledge.[18] According to Śivāditya ṇa is that which produces or right knowledge.[19]
The history of the ⲹ system extends over many centuries. At the earliest stage it has not developed as a system but a means of arriving at the real meanings of Vedic words. There were disputations and debates among scholars to find out real meanings of the Vedic texts in earlier times. When disputations began among the supporters of different schools of thought; they tried to defeat one another by using it. Such disputations happened in the time of 貹Ծṣa and the art of disputation was then recognized as a subject of study which is regarded to as Vākovākya.[20] This is the earliest mention of ⲹ system.
The first systematic work of the ⲹ system is the ⲹsūtra of Gautama or ṣa岹. A large number of works were written after ⲹsūtra for the development of this system. The accurate date of the ⲹsūtra is difficult to ascertain. According to D.N. Shastri, the date of ⲹsūtra may be put in the middle or at the close of the second century A.D.[21] This is the primary text of the Prācina ⲹ school. This work is divided into five chapters, each of which is again divided in to two sections called ĀԾ첹. There are a large number of Sutras.
The main subjects dealt in the ⲹsūtra are:
- ʰṇa (the means of knowledge);
- Prameya (the object of knowledge),
- 岹 (discussion),
- Avayava (members of a syllogism) and
- Anyamata-貹īṣ� (the examination of the doctrines of other systems of philosophy).
This works contains an examination of various philosophical doctrines. For example, in book III, chapter II, there is a criticism of the ṃkⲹ doctrine of knowledge (buddhi) and the Bauddha doctrine of momentariness; in book IV, chapter I, there is a review of Buddhist doctrine of ܲԲⲹ and also the Vedāntic view of 貹ṇām岹 etc.
The first commentator of the ⲹsūtra is ٲⲹԲ and the name of his work is ⲹbhāṣya. He is also known as Pakṣilasvāmin who mentioned in his work the views of the earlier ⾱첹. According to S.N. Dasgupta, his date is about 4th century A.D.[22] Rādhākrishnan also accepts the same date.[23]
According to Karl H. Potter,
“T ⲹbhāṣya is not only the first commentary on the ⲹsūtra that is still extant, it is also the first to which we find any reference�.[24] There are many commentaries on ⲹbhāṣya.
ⲹ-پ첹 is a sub-commentary on ⲹsūtra written by Uddyotakara. The date of Uddyotakara is about 635 A.D.[25] In this commentary, the author develops many new arguments and sometimes presents new or alternative explanations for the same ūٰ. “T main object which prompted Uddyotakara to write his sub-commentary was to oppose Dignāga, 岵ܲԲ and other Buddhist logicians that preceded him.�[26]
Dharmakīrti in his ⲹbindu defended Dignāga and refuted the views of Uddyotakara. Towards the first half of the ninth century, 峦貹پ Ѿś tried to re-establish the ⲹ doctrines propounded by Gautama, ٲⲹԲ, and Uddyotakara. He wrote ⲹپ첹tātparyatīkā. 峦貹پ was a versatile, genius and prolific writer. He wrote commentaries on the works of other philosophical schools like ṃkⲹ, Vedanta and Mīmāṃṣā. In his work, 峦貹پ has established the supremacy of ⲹ on other systems by refuting the opposite views. 峦貹پ does not always followed ٲⲹԲ or Uddyotakara for interpreting different ūٰs of ⲹsūtra.
ⲹmañjarī of Jayanta ṭṭ is an independent work on the ⲹsūtra. According to Radhakrishnan, the time of Jayanta ṭṭ is 10th century A.D.[27] The author’s interpretation of ⲹ doctrine is quite independent. The author has referred to many schools of Indian Philosophy like, Buddhism, Jainism, Mīmāṃṣā, ṃkⲹ, ձԳٲ, Ś etc.
ⲹsāra of Bhāsarvajña is another important treatise. This treatise was written in about 10th century A.D.[28] In this treatise, author mentions the three ṇas, ٲⲹṣa, ԳܳԲ and ś岹.[29] The author himself wrote a commentary on his work called ⲹbhāṣya.
岹ⲹ峦ⲹ, also known as Udayakara was one of the greatest ⾱첹. He flourished after 峦貹پ Ѿś. He was the last of ⾱첹 who belong to the old school of ⲹ (ʰ峦īԲԲⲹ). After that he flourished the Navyaⲹ school. It is also said that Udayana prepared the way for emergence of Navyaⲹ. He wrote a sub-commentary named ⲹپ첹tātparyapariśūddhi on 峦貹پ’s ⲹپ첹tātparyaṭīkā. He refuted the criticisms of the Buddhist logicians against 峦貹پ Ѿś in this work. Udayana also wrote some independent works on ⲹ system. In his ⲹ-kusumāñjalī, he has forwarded arguments to prove the existence of God. Another important ⲹ work of Udayana is Āٳٲٳٱ첹. In this work he tries to establish the ⲹ-doctrine of Soul against the attack of Buddhists. The time of Udayana is supposed to be the latter half of the11th century A.D.[30] ղ岹Ჹ wrote an important commentary named ǻī on Udayana’s ⲹ-kusumāñjalī.[31] ղԲ wrote a commentary named ʰś on Udayana’s ٱ貹ⲹ貹śܻ.
The 쾱첹ṣ� of ղ岹Ჹ is another important treatise on ⲹ system. Trilocana, a brilliant ⾱첹 wrote ⲹmañjarī. His time is speculated as about 900 A.D.[32] Though the title ⲹmañjarī is identical with the title of Jayanta ṭṭ’s great work on ⲹ, the work is different in nature. However, it has given rise to some confusion also.
Maṇikaṇṭha Ѿś wrote a work, named ⲹratna.It is a logical text on the argumentative aspects of ⲹ. Visvanātha’s ⲹsūtravṛtti (17th century A.D.) is another important work of this system.[33] In this work, the author discusses the essential structure of the ⲹ syllogism.
The above mentioned treatises of ⲹ system follow the ūٰs of Gautama and maintain the spirit of these ūٰs. Thus, these works discuss religion and metaphysic together with purely logical problems. Hence, in these works we find discussions on the concept of the self and its rebirth, God and the world as also the logical problems, concerning the nature and means of knowledge etc. But later on the ⲹ works started to give stress on pure logic and dialectics. As a result there developed a new trend among the ⲹ scholars which is termed as Navya-ⲹ (Neo Logic) and the former works are regarded as ʰ峦īԲ ⲹ (Old ⲹ).
Footnotes and references:
[1]:
traividyebhyasٰī� vidyāt daṇḍanītiñca śāśvatīm/ Աīṣiī� cātmavidyā� vārtārambhāṃścalokata�// ѲԳܲṃh, 7.13
[4]:
cf. Vidyabhusana, S.C., A History of Indian Logic, p. 5
[5]:
yo’vamanyeta te mule hetu-śāstrāśrayāddvija�/ ѲԳܲṃh, 2.11
[6]:
Ѳٲ, Ā徱貹, 1.67
[8]:
anantarañca vaktrabhyo vedāstasya viniḥsṛtā�/
[9]:
nyāyatantro anekāni taistairuktāni vādibhi�/ hetvāgamasamācārairyadukta� tadupāsyatām// Ѳٲ, Sāntiparva, 21.22
[11]:
cf. Reyana, Ruth, Dictionary of Oriental Philosophy, Vol. 1, p.136
[12]:
Vidyabhusana, S.C., A History of Indian Logic, p.40
[13]:
ṇairthaparīkṣaṇa� Բⲹ�/ ⲹbhāṣya, 1.1.1
[14]:
cf. prameyādīnā� tāvatpadārthānā� � tatvajñāna� ṇatatvajñānādhīnam. ⲹپ첹tātparyatīkā, 1.1.1
[15]:
Dasgupta, S.N., A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, p.277
[16]:
upalavdhisādhanāni ṇāni/ ⲹbhāṣya, 1.1.3
[17]:
ⲹپ첹, 1.1.10
[18]:
cf. ṇe tṛprameyoścaritārthatvāt � acaritārtha� tu ṇam atastadevopalavdhisādhanamiti. Ibid
[21]:
Shastri, D.N., The Philosophy of ⲹ-Vaiśeṣika and Its Conflict with the
[22]:
cf. Dasgupta, S.N., A History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. I, p.307
[23]:
cf. Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p.38
[24]:
Potter, Karl H., Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p.239
[25]:
cf. Vidyabhusana, S.C., A History of Indian Logic, p.124
[26]:
Vidyabhusana, S.C., Ibid., p.125
[27]:
cf. Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p. 40
[28]:
Ibid.
[29]:
Ibid
[30]:
cf. Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p. 523
[31]:
Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p. 26
[32]:
cf. Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p. 396
[33]:
Radhakrishnan, S., Indian Philosophy, Vol. II, p. 27