365bet

A History of Indian Philosophy Volume 4

Indian Pluralism

by Surendranath Dasgupta | 1949 | 186,278 words | ISBN-13: 9788120804081

This page describes the philosophy of inference (anumana): a concept having historical value dating from ancient India. This is the second part in the series called the “madhva logic�, originally composed by Surendranath Dasgupta in the early 20th century.

Go directly to: Footnotes.

Part 2 - Inference (anumāna)

The cause of inference is a faultless reason (through which by virtue of its association anything can be ascertained). The nature of this association or concomitance is described by Jaya-īٳ as being inseparable concomitance (). ղ-īٳ urges in the Tarka-ṇḍ that this inseparable concomitance ought really to mean contradiction of experience leading to inadmissible assumption or implication (anupapatti). When anything experienced in a particular space-time relation must be invalid except on the assumption of some other thing, in some other space-time relation, it must be admitted that such a particular relation subsisting between the two is a relation of concomitance (پ), leading to the inference of the latter through the former[1].

ղ-īٳ urges that this view of. inference has also been supported by Madhva in his ʰṇa-ṣaṇa, where he says that the residual method (貹śṣa) is the essential method in all cases of valid inference[2]. Reduction to absurdity in regard to any valid experience is what necessitates the supposition in an act of inference.[3] Jaya-īٳ in his ʰṇa-paddhati has indeed defined concomitance (پ) as inseparability (-); this inseparable concomitance cannot be described as being in all cases agreement in absence, i.e., the absence of the reason, hetu, in all cases of the absence of the probandum (), or the inferred entity; for there are cases where, in spite of the absence of such negative instances, inference is possible, e.g., sound is expressible on account of its being an object of knowledge; now here no such negative instance is available where there would be no expression; hence in such cases of impossible-negative (𱹲Ա⾱) inferences the above definition of concomitance, which requires the existence of negative instances for the ascertainment of concomitance, would not apply. Also no kind of spatial association of the reason and consequence (ⲹ) can be urged as being an indispensable condition of concomitance: for there can be the inference of rain in the upper part of a country from perceiving a rise of water in the river in the lower part, and there is no spatial contiguity between the reason and consequence. So the main point in concomitance determining inference is the reduction of an incontrovertible experience into an impossibility, which necessitates the assumption of the inferred entity. It is this which has also been described as the law of unconditional and invariable association (󲹳ⲹ-niyama). In the well-known example of fire and smoke what is described as the unconditional and invariable coexistence of the absence of smoke in all cases of the absence of fire is also a case of reductio ad absurdum (anupapatti). It would apply with equal force in the cases of impossibfe-negatives (𱹲Ա⾱) ; for there also the impossible absence of the consequence would render the reason absurd; and hence the assumption of the consequence is necessary.

ղ-īٳ refutes at great length the definition of inference given by Gaṅgeśa in his Tattva-Գ峾ṇi, where he explains concomitance as the coexistence of consequence and reason as qualified by the fact of the absence of the latter in each case of the absence of the former. Had it not been for the fact that in inferences of the type of impossible-negatives (𱹲Ա⾱) no negative instances are available where we might have been acquainted with cases of absence of the consequence being also cases of absence of the reason (sādhyā屹vad-avṛttitvam), Gaṅgeśa would have been glad to define concomitance (پ) as unconditional and invariable non-existence of the reason in all cases of the non-existence of the consequence (sādhyā屹vad-avṛttitvam). But owing to the above difficulty Gaṅgeśa was forced to define concomitance as coexistence (峾󾱰첹ṇy) of the consequence and reason where the reason is also qualified as the repository of the negation of all possible conditions which could invalidate its unconditional and invariable relation to the consequence (ⲹ)[4]. The insight of Gaṅgeśa in formulating such a definition consists in this, that he thinks that universal existence of the reason in case of the consequence is alone sufficient for an inference of the latter from the former, provided that the reason is pure and unmixed by the presence of any other entity. It is the presence of other entities mixed with the reason that may invalidate its universal coexistence with the consequence; so, if that could be eliminated, then mere universal existence of the reason in cases of the consequence would be sufficient to establish a relation of concomitance between the former and the latter.

ղ-īٳ, however, points out that the existence of the reason in cases of the consequence is not universally valid in all cases of inference. Thus in the inference of rain in the upper regions from perceiving a rise of water in the river in the lower regions there is no spatial coexistence of the reason in the consequence; so also in the inference that the constellation dzṇ� will shortly rise in the east because the constellation ṛtپ has already risen. In all such cases and in all cases of inference the view of reductio ad absurdum (anupapatti) can always define concomitance in the best possible way and therefore can also serve as the best ground for all kinds of inference, including the class known as impossible-negatives (𱹲Ա⾱). For in the example given of that class, “this is expressible because it is an object of knowledge�, we can argue that the denial of non-expressibility is a necessary postulate for the validity of the incontrovertible experience of its being an object of knowledge[5]. An objection may be raised that, non-expressibility being as fictitious an entity as a round square, there would be no meaning in further denying it. To this ղ-īٳ’s reply is that negation may apply even to the fictitious and the non-existent (峾ṇi첹)[6].

It is evident that this view of concomitance is a later development of theory by ղ-īٳ. For Jaya-īٳ, in his ʰṇa-paddhati, describes concomitance as being inseparable existence (), which he explains as invariable coexistence (󲹳ⲹ-Ծⲹ) and also as invariable relation (avyabhicarita� saṃbandha�)[7]. 岹Բ, however, in his commentary on the ʰṇa-paddhati, holds that this 󲹳ⲹ-Ծⲹ of Jaya-īٳ must be interpreted to mean the reductio ad absurdum of ղ-īٳ; otherwise it would be evident to all that his view of concomitance has been intended by the above definition of Jaya-īٳ; and he supports his view by pointing out that both in the ʰṇa-ṣaṇa and in his commentary on the ʰṇa-ṣaṇa Jaya-īٳ has included inference by residues (貹śṣa) and implication (ٳ貹ٳپ) within inference, as he thought that the methods of these are practically methods of inference itself[8]. But this only proves that 貹śṣa and ٳ貹ٳپ are also kinds of inference and not that the method of anupapatti involved in them should be regarded as being the only possible form of inference. Had he thought this to be so, he would certainly have mentioned it and would not have limited his definition of concomitance to invariable coexistence (󲹳ⲹ-niyama). Chalari-śeṣācārya, who faithfully follows the footprints of Jaya-īٳ, often repeating his language also, explains this invariable coexistence of Jaya-īٳ as “where there is smoke, there is fire�; but he remarks that this invariable coexistence means only the existence of an invariable relation of the reason to the consequence (atra sāhacarya� heto� sādhyena saṃbandha-mātra� vivakṣitam), and not merely existence in the same place (峾󾱰첹ṇy). Coexistence therefore is said to mean here unfailing relation to the consequence (avyabhicarita-ⲹ-saṃbandho پ�), and this is پ [9]. He also refers to Gaṅgeśa’s definition of پ, noted above, and points out that this definition of پ would be inapplicable in those instances of inference where there is no spatial coexistence (e.g., the inference of rain in the upper regions from the rise of water in the river in the lower regions)[10]. He points out on the strength of such instances that concomitance cannot be defined as coexistence (峾󾱰첹ṇy), but is an unfailing relation which may hold between a cause and an effect existing in different places. On the strength of these instances Chalari-śeṣācārya argues in favour of concomitance without coexistence (vyadhikaraṇa-پ) as being possible, and therefore advocates the dropping of the coexistence as a necessary condition of concomitance. ղ-īٳ seems to have profited by these remarks and, instead of remaining content with “unfailing relation� of Chaḷari-śeṣācārya, explained this “unfailing relation� as being the definite relation of reductio ad absurdum (anupapatti)[11].

Footnotes and references:

[back to top]

[1]:

yad-deśa-kāla-saṃbaddhasya yasya yad-deśa-kāla-saṃbaddhena yena vinānupapattis tasyiva tena saha پ�.
      Tarka-ṇḍ
(MS., p. 1).

[2]:

pariśeṣo’rthāpattir amumānam ity aviśeṣa�.
      ʰṇa-ṣaṇa

      and ʰṇa-ṣaṇa-ṭīkā, p. 27.

[3]:

anumānam api āvaśyakānupapattyaiva gamakam.
      Tarka-ṇḍ
(MS.,p. 2).

[4]:

pratiyogy-asamānādhikaraṇa-yat-samānādhikaraṇātyantā屹-pratiyogitā-vacchedakāvacchinna� yan na bhavati tena sama� tasya 峾󾱰첹ṇy� پ�.
      Tattva-Գ峾ṇi,
Part II, p. 100 (ed. 1888, Bibliotheca Indica).

[5]:

ida� vācya� jñeyatvāt kevalānvayi anumānam.

[6]:

tatra sādhyā屹sya asattvād eva sādhyābhāve sati sādhanasya yopapattis tad-a屹-rūpānupapatte� sattvāt; manmate’prāmāṇikasyāpi niṣedha-prati-yogitvāt.
      Tarka-ṇḍ
(MS., p. 6).

[7]:

ʰṇa-paddhati, p. 30.

[8]:

anupapatter پtva� ca pramāṇa-lakṣaṇe pariśeṣārthāpatti� anumā-viśeṣa ity atrārthāpattir iva anumānam api āvaśyakānupapattyaiva gamakam ity uktatvāt.
      Tarka-ṇḍ
(MS., pp. 1-2).
      Also ʰṇa-ṣaṇa-ṭīkā, pp. 5-7.

[9]:

Cf. Gaṅgeśa’s alternative definition of پ in the section on Viśeṣa-پ:

yat-saṃbandhitāvacchedaka-rūpavattva� yasya tasya sā پ�.
      Tattva-Գ峾ṇi,
Part II, p. 156.

[10]:

na tu samāṇādhikaraṇyam eva.
      ʰṇa-candrikā
, p. 8 a.

[11]:

ʰṇa-candrikā, pp. 8a, 9.

Let's grow together!

I humbly request your help to keep doing what I do best: provide the world with unbiased sources, definitions and images. Your donation direclty influences the quality and quantity of knowledge, wisdom and spiritual insight the world is exposed to.

Let's make the world a better place together!

Like what you read? Help to become even better: