Philosophy of language in the Five Nikayas
by K.T.S. Sarao | 2013 | 141,449 words
This page relates ‘Language and Knowledge� of the study of the Philosophy of language in the Five Nikayas, from the perspective of linguistics. The Five Nikayas, in Theravada Buddhism, refers to the five books of the Sutta Pitaka (“Basket of Sutra�), which itself is the second division of the Pali Tipitaka of the Buddhist Canon (literature).
Go directly to: Footnotes.
4. Language and Knowledge
In chapter two I have brought out the various definitions of the different points of view of linguists, philosophers, psychologists, and so on (see §2.3). In this section, an attempt has been made to deal with and critically study the language and knowledge as reflected in the Five ⲹ. It, however, firstly needs further to examine and discuss the philosophy of language; that is, the language of thought in particular, and the knowledge of language in general.
Language is known as a unique faculty of man’s knowledge coordinated to the senses and the intellect. It is a form of rational communication, of communication of thought. Philosophers have provided many different accounts of what languages might be. Some think of languages as structured by formal logical relations; others prefer accounts based on the idea of speech acts. Davidson, however, has denied the existence of languages if these are understood as governed by conventions that determine the connections between words and what they might mean. Several philosophers have made claims about what kind of features language must have for it to be learnable by creatures, like us, with finite abilities. According to Tenesini (2007: 87), “Fodor has used these considerations to argue for a language of thought, Dummett to argue against semantic realism, and Davidson to argue for a recursive theory of meaning. Chomsky (1968) proposes that linguistic theory should explain the mental processes that underlie the use of language. He is the pioneer who placed linguistics at the core of studies of the mind in affirming that language is a code that represents our hidden inner thoughts, a ‘mirror of mind�. Dialectically, Stcherbatsky (1999: 458) suggests that “language is not a separate source of knowledge� but “an indirect cognition of reality.� It is something what to be used to convey our knowledge or logically our indirect knowledge through inference. Thus, as being viewed above, “language mirrors human mental processes or shapes the flow and character of thought� (Chomsky 1968: 1). In fact, as Descartes himself quite correctly observed, “language is a species-specific human possession, and even at low levels of intelligence, at pathological levels, we find a command of language that is totally unattainable by an ape that may, in other respects, surpass a human imbecile in problem-solving ability and other adaptive behavior� (Chomsky 1968: 9).
Before embarking to study the knowledge and the knowledge of language, it is necessary to present briefly the Truth-table which provides all the possible combinations of the truth-values taken by complex truth functional sentences given the values assigned to their atomic sentential constituents. A truth-table, for instance, shows that the conjunction of the sentences ‘it is raining� and ‘it is windy� is true when it is both raining and windy, and false in all other cases. Thus, the truth-table is illustrated below:
Table 1: Truth-Table
It is raining | It is windy | It is raining and it is windy |
T | T | T |
T | F | F |
F | T | F |
F | F | F |
As the table shown, the truth-tables are used to illustrate the meaning of truth-functional sentential connectives. They also offer an effective method for testing the validity of arguments in propositional logic.
Based on Huarte’s distinguishing three levels of intelligence; that is, (i) “docile wit�: the lowest level; (ii) the normal human intelligence: the next higher level; and (iii) normal human minds: the highest level that “assisted by the subject alone, without the help of any body, they will produce a thousand of conceits they never heard spoke of � inventing and saying such things as they never heard from their masters, nor any mouth� (Chomsky 1968: 8), Chomsky goes to conclude that “normal human intelligence is capable of acquiring knowledge through its own internal resources, perhaps making use of the data of sense but going on to construct a cognitive system in terms of concepts and principles that are developed on independent grounds; and it is capable of generating new thoughts and of finding appropriate and novel ways of expressing them, in ways that entirely transcend any training or experience� (Chomsky 1968: 8). A person’s knowledge of language, according to Chomsky, “is representable as a stored set of patterns, overlearned through constant repetition and detailed training, with innovation being at most a matter of ‘analogy� � [and] the normal use of language is not only innovative and potentially infinite in scope, but also free from the control of detectable stimuli, either external or internal. It is because of this freedom from stimulus control that language can serve as instrument of thought and self-expression, as it does not only for exceptionally gifted and talented, but also, in fact, for every normal human� (Chomsky 1968: 10-11). Chomsky (1968) continues to argue that “a phrase corresponds to a complex idea and a sentence is subdivided into consecutive phrases, which are further subdivided into phrases, and so on, until the level of word is reached.� And he takes an example to illustrate this: the sentence “Invisible God created the visible world� contains the subject “invisible God� and the predicate “created the visible world,� the latter contains a complex idea “the visible world� and the verb “created,� and so on. In the example just given, “Invisible God created the visible world,� the deep structure consists of a system of three propositions, “that God is invisible,� “that he created the world,� “that the world is visible.� Thus, “the deep structure is related to the surface structure by certain mental oprations -in modern terminology, by grammatical transformations. Each language can be regarded as a particular relation between sound and meaning. � The grammar of a language must contain a system of rules that characterizes deep and surface structures and the transformational relation between them, and that does so over an infinite domain of paired deep and surface structures� (Chomsky 1968: 15).
A language, as Chomsky (1968: 23) observed, is a “habit structure� or “a network of associative connections� or “that knowledge of language is merely a matter of “knowing how,� a skill expressible as a system of disposetions to respond. Accordingly, knowledge of language must develop slowly through repetition and training, its apparent complexity resulting from the proliferation of very simple elements rather than from deeper principles of mental organization that may be as inaccessible to intro-spection as the mechanism of digestion or coordinated movement.�
In order to achieve progress in the study of language and human cognitive faculties in general it is necessary first to establish “psychic distance� from the “mental facts,� and then to explore the possibilities for developing explanatory theories, whatever they may suggest with regard to the complexity and abstractness of the underlying mechanism. For Chomsky, “the person who has acquired knowledge of a language has internalized a system of rules that relate sound and meaning in a particular way� (Chomsky 1968: 23). It is evidently that knowledge of language–the internalized system of rules–according to Chomsky is “only one of the many factors that determine how an utterance will be used or understood in a particular situation.�
Drawing upon a fast growing body of research, it can be argued that there in fact exist two types of knowledge; that is, direct and indirect. It means that knowledge originates either from the senses, perception, or the intellect, conception. The knowledge derived from language is known as indirect knowledge because it does not belong to the domain of sensation. Language, though, somewhat belongs to intellectual, inferential, conceptual, and dialectical domains whereas the real knowledge or direct knowledge as the ultimate truth is pure, unintelligible, unutterable and non-dialectical. With a varied and the most extensive appraisal of the Five ⲹ, specially the Samyutta ⲹ, the reality or the ultimate truth itself is vivid and pure but without the language, the man cannot touch it. As Varshney (17th ed. 2009: 1) asserts “without language man would have remain only a dumb animal.�
Philosophical discussions describe clearly and succinctly that language in its intermediary function has aspects of epistemology (theory of knowing) and ontology (theory of being). As a sharp tool of knowledge, it is regarded to operate in a characteristically dialectical process of veiling and revealing truths and is in the process sometimes identified even with the reality that it seeks to represent. It fulfills an interpretative function in the process of effectively apprehending as well as comprehending the applied experience.
The relationship of language to the real knowledge albeit happens to be indirect and distant rather than close. In general, it is pointed out that language is not only an interpretative knowledge of the world and a conferral or comparison of meaning to life but also a means of access to the ultimately reality thus leading to the final liberated goal. For this purpose, the Buddha with the immeasurable wisdom aims to utilize various ways and manners to enable the people understand the truth and through which they can reach to the right and highest knowledge.
Knowledge thus can be viewed in a sense as basically an understanding of or information about a subject which is either represented in a person’s mind or possessed by people on a whole. It also means awareness, a discovery of something. Thus, as points out by Sasaki (1992) “knowledge refers to the analysis of an object, and such knowledge called objective knowledge. This kind of knowledge can be accumulated. It cannot, however, be termed Buddhist knowledge as far as it concerns objective analysis.� This can easily be recognized if we pay attention to the fine distinction between the scientific knowledge, that can be accumulated and obtained by experience or study, and the religious knowledge, that is wisdom or insight rising from awareness and enlightenment, a discriminating knowledge or intuitive apprehension. One possessing the scientific knowledge is the improbable one who has wisdom. Since Buddhism attaches an importance to wisdom based on the faculty, which apprehends the truth of the Buddha’s teaching more than just the accumulated scientific knowledge. Wisdom in Buddhism sense, according to Sasaki (1992), is divided into two concepts: transcendental knowledge (ñṇa) and knowledge-to-exercised (貹ññ).[1]
ñṇa ‘transcendental knowledge� is particularly used in the context of the understanding of doctrines. In terms of the Buddhist epistemology, tradition (anussava) is neither by itself a valid form of knowledge, nor are sense-perception or reason the reliable means of knowledge until the distorting influence of unwholesome mental factors, which are rooted in greed (岵), hatred (dosa), and delusion (moha), have been eliminated. Once this has been achieved, one who reflects with right and wise attention (yoniso manasikāra) will perceive with the proper mode of cognitive awareness and see things ‘as they really are� (ⲹٳūٲ) (Majjhima ⲹ, Sutta number 149.9). In such sense, ñṇa often occurs in intensive couple-compounds with terms of sight as cakkhu ‘eye�, for example: �-첹ṇa ñṇa-karaṇa�, ‘opening our eyes and thus producing knowledge� (that is, giving us the eye of knowledge (a mental eye)), or with dassana (sight, view) as in ñṇadassana, ‘knowledge and vision�, ‘full vision�, insight given by knowledge that is for ‘one who knows and sees�[2] (Majjhima ⲹ, Sutta number 2). This is one of the features of Arahantship.[3] Generally speaking, ñṇa is relative to common experience and perception (ññ) is necessary for the formation of ñṇa, as it precedes ñṇa.
ʲññ ‘knowledge-to-exercised�, which will be discussed in great detail on the next section, is an important concept in Buddhist epistemology. It is often translated as ‘wisdom� but closer in meaning to insight, discriminating knowledge, or intuitive apprehension, comprising all the higher faculties of cognition. It is the faculty which apprehends the truth of Buddhist teachings not as a mere understanding of doctrines but as ‘coming-to-know� and ‘coming-to-be�. In other words, 貹ññ is not dialectic but an exercise of thought on matter of practice. It is not mere insight or intuition, but conduct accompanied by insight; it is a term of practical import (C.A.F. Rhys Davids 1978: 265). Although all beings possess 貹ññ, it is usually the underdeveloped that needs to be cultivated through the practice of insight meditation (貹). In the three standard stages[4] which lead to arahanship, it occupies the highest and last stage; that is, the third division 貹ññ-kkhandha ‘code of intellectual duties or practice of the attainment of highest knowledge�. Obviously, this can found in the Mahāvedalla Sutta (Majjhima ⲹ, Sutta number 43) at which 貹ññ is regarded as the practiced knowledge (屹ٲ), a wisely understanding about the Four Noble Truths. In the Abhidhamma, 貹ññ is classified as one of the mental functions (cetasika), and is defined as the analytical discrimination of phenomena (dhamma-pavicaya).
The distinction between ñṇa and 貹ññ is very multi-polar. In the Early Buddhism, this distinction was not very clear as sometimes they were used as synonymous. However, the Abhidhamma period onwards it became evident clear. In Abhidhamma, 貹ññ came to mean the subject’s knowing (貹Բ). In contract, ñԲ came to mean the object to be known (ñٲ) . Thus, ñԲ is the object, while 貹ññ belongs to the subject. The endeavour to attain ñԲ thus presupposes 貹ññ (Sasaki 1992: 92). Thus, 貹ññ obviously has a broader sense than ñṇa. This distinction becomes clearer during the period of commentaries. In an attempt to bring out the dynamics of 貹ññ more persuasively, the ٳٳī presents two characteristics of 貹ññ� s: (i) illuminating (DzԲ) and (ii) knowing or understanding (貹Բna) as follows:
Hence, the Elder has said: Just as when a man, your majesty, introduces an oil-lamp into a dark house, the lamp so introduced disperses the darkness, produces light, sheds lustre, makes objects visible, so, your majesty, 貹ññ as it arises dispels the darkness of ignorance, produces the light of understanding (), sheds the lustre of ñṇa, makes plain the Ariyan Facts. Thus, your majesty, 貹ññ has illuminating as its characteristic.
And this was said by the ٳ貹پ (ܳٳٲ): ‘It knows; thus, brother, it is in consequence called 貹ññ. And what does it know? This is ill�, and so on. Thus it should be expanded. And thus knowing should be regarded as the characteristic of 貹ññ.
(Sasaki 1992: 97)
Thus, 貹ññ� s characteristic is quite illuminating, its function is to break up the darkness, and its manifestation is to shed the sheen of ñṇa or to produce the light of understanding (). Ñṇa as a whole is considered as a consequence of 貹ññ. In addition, the commentator also gave two further etymological interpretations of 貹ññ that are: (i) 貹ññpana ‘to make known or to indicate�; and (ii) 貹Բ پ ‘to know the object from the viewpoint of impermanence (Ծ), suffering (ܰ) and non-self (Բٳ)�. These two meanings are closely related to each other and turn to the same fact that due to 貹ññ the nature of existing things would be made explicitly known. ʲññ, thus, signifies the spiritual wisdom which embraces the fundamental truths of the essence of human existence (Sasaki 1992:92-3).
The distinction between the static and dynamic states of ñṇa and 貹ññ becomes more pure in dzԴǻ岹ī. According to this commentary, 貹ññ operates by virtue of function (kicca) and object (ṇa) while ñṇa has for its object (dhamma) . It means that in order to operate 貹ññ must firstly have an action on the subjective side and the object on the objective side. With the object alone, 貹ññ is considered not to work at all. Ñṇa is included in the object to be known and practised by 貹ññ. And thus, ñṇa is regarded as the static product and ideal to be obtained, while 貹ññ is subjective, dynamic and functional. In terms of spiritual exercise, the important thing is not merely the ideal or result, but rather the way to approach the ideal. Whether the achievement of the ideal is realized or not rest on the ability of the practitioner. Ñṇa, therefore, will be of significance only when it is considered in relation to the functional 貹ññ. In other words, the ideal must be achieved by the practical: ñṇa must be achieved by 貹ññ, it is assimilated in 貹ññ. In order to elucidate this distinction, the venerable Buddhaghosa compared 貹ññ with ññ ‘perception� and viññṇa ‘consciousness�. This comparison showed that ññ refers to the perception of a colourful object, whereas viññṇa means the perception of a multitude of appearances. These two terms concern the analytical perception of the object. ʲññ, on the other hand, means to distinctively know (貹Բna) ‘the religious significance� of the object.
The view that ñṇa as a consequence, and 貹ññ as a means of the Early Buddhism and the ճ岹 school are also found in the ś and its commentary of the پ岹 school. This school believes that 貹ññ is imminent and refers to the way to be cultivated, while ñṇa is transcendental and a consequence or a result to be attained. Apart from the arguments for the distinction of the two concepts, the پ岹 school goes further into the details of their intertwined relationship.
The commentator Yaśomitra pointed out three types of functions of 貹ññ (Skt, ñ):
ʲññ performs its function as acceptance of the truth at the first stage, as the decision at the second stage, and as the investigation at the last one. These three kinds of functions have a connecting link between each other, representing the stepping-forward of 貹ññ in function from acceptance to investigation. Thus, ñṇa here is considered as one of the qualities of the dynamic and functional 貹ññ, being therefore assimilated by and intertwined with 貹ññ. The Sarvāstivādins, in addition, attempt a combination and formulate the philosophy of model form by which 貹ññ and ñṇa come into unity. They try to express how the knowledge-to-be-cultivated (that is, 貹ññ) is combined and unified with its product (that is, ñṇa). This unification is termed as . According to the , a concept of means a type of form (ū貹) which remains even after the disappearance of the object. ʲññ denotes the essential nature of and the basis of ñṇa. In other words, is a model form in which 貹ññ and ñṇa come into unity. It consists of these two counterparts. It is obvious that in the پ岹 school 貹ññ includes both functions, psychological and philosophical. When 貹ññ is taken as knowledge to determine the characteristics of dhamma, it is a psychological function. On the contrary, when 貹ññ is taken as knowledge to be cultivated and exercised, it is a philosophical function. It is a means, by which one can remove defilements out of his mind and can reach the final goal.
The notion that 貹ññ is as a means to remove defilements can also be seen in the Ѳṇg첹 school, preceding ѲԲ Buddhism. Later, with the development of ѲԲ Buddhism the concept of 貹ññ has come to refer to light. Its original meaning ‘the knowledge to be exercised� has come into focus on the basis of the Bodhisattva’s ideal, which emphasizes the human activities, encourages altruism and universal compassion.
A Bodhisattva must perfect the Ten Transcendental Perfections (ٲ):[5]
- generosity (Բ),
- morality (ī),
- patience (khanti),
- courage (viriya),
- meditation (),
- intuitive insight (貹ññ),
- skilful means (ⲹܲ),
- vow (ʲԾԲ)
- power (bala), and
- knowledge (ñṇa).
The sixth Perfection, the perfection of insight (貹ññ), is the central element of the ѲԲ Path. The Mahāyānist experience provided the basis for the identification of the Buddha with ultimate reality (Skt, ñ). Furthermore, the pursuit of the ñ experience is one and the same with the quest for Buddhahood. Here, ʰñ represents the practitioner’s recognition of his own potential Buddhahood which is cultivated by himself. The cultivation of insight results in the direct realization of emptiness (ññٳ) and is regarded by many ѲԲ texts especially the ʰñ Sūtra, the foundation of the ѲԲ. Accordingly, the ʰñ literature was innovative in two principal ways. First, it advocates the Bodhisattva ideal as the highest form of the religious life, and second the ‘insight� it teaches is into the emptiness and non-production of phenomena (dhammas), rather than into their substantial (albeit impermanent) mode of being as previously assumed.
There are some distinctions between the ⲹ첹 and the VijñԲvāda school on the basis of the ñpārami (Skt, ñ, ‘Perfection of Wisdom�) idea. The ⲹ첹 school developed the intellectual self-training through knowledge, emphasizing thereby the theoretical structure built round 貹ññ. The VijñԲvāda School, on the other hand, developed the inner experience through yoga accruing upon the treading of ñṇa. For VijñԲvāda school, ñṇa represents the pure knowledge realized by the enlightenment where discriminative knowledge is converted into non-discriminative knowledge. Enlightenment consequently means a conversion from the experimental world based upon discriminative knowledge into non-discriminative knowledge. Thus, the term ñṇa in this context concerns the transcendental and consequential knowledge while 貹ññ concerns the immanent and existential knowledge related to the exercise of the practitioner. It is for this reason that the knowledge of the Buddha is always represented as �Buddhañṇa� and not as �Buddha貹ññ�. In short, this distinction between the ⲹ첹 and the VijñԲvāda is after all an expression merely of different emphasis of two sides to Buddhist experience, the theoretical and the inner experiential. This means that Buddhist experience involves not only seeing that the reality is ‘emptiness� but also seeing this in inner experience.[6]
We have seen two types of knowledge above. It should be recalled here that direct and indirect knowledge. That knowledge originates either from the senses, perception, or the intellect, conception is called direct knowledge. That knowledge derived from language is known as indirect knowledge because it does not belong to the domain of sensation. In Sutta NiԲssaṃyatta ‘Connected Discourses on Causation� (Samyutta ⲹ, Sutta number 12) in order to make bhikkhus become the noble disciples the Buddha brings out two kinds of knowledge–knowledge of the principle and knowledge of entailment. That “he is called a noble discipline who is accomplished in view, accomplished in vision, who has arrived at this true Dhamma, who sees this true Dhamma, who possesses a trainee’s knowledge, a trainee’s true knowledge, who has entered the stream of the Dhamma, a noble one with penetrative wisdom, one who stands squarely before the door to the Deathless� (Samyutta ⲹ, Sutta number 12.33).
And the Blessed One also teaches cases of knowledge as follows:
“Bhikkhus, I will teach you forty-four cases of knowledge. Bhikkhus, what are the forty-four cases of knowledge? Knowledge of aging-anddeath, knowledge of its origin, knowledge of its cessation, knowledge of the way leading to its cessation. Knowledge of birth... Knowledge of existence... Knowledge of clinging... Knowledge of craving... Knowledge of feeling... Knowledge of contact... Knowledge of the six sense bases... Knowledge of name-and-form... Knowledge of consciousness... Knowledge of volitional formations, knowledge of their origin, knowledge of their cessation, knowledge of the way leading to their cessation. These, bhikkhus, are the forty-four cases of knowledge.
“And what, bhikkhus, is aging-and-death?... (definition as above)... Thus this aging and this death are together called aging-and-death. With the arising of birth there is the arising of aging-and-death. With the cessation of birth there is the cessation of aging-and-death. This Noble Eightfold Path is the way leading to the cessation of aging-anddeath; that is, right view... right concentration. (Samyutta ⲹ, Sutta number 12.33)
And, further, the Buddha goes on teachings the cases of knowledge:
“Bhikkhus, I will teach you seventy-seven cases of knowledge. Bhikkhus, what are seventy-seven cases of knowledge? The knowledge: ‘Aging-and-death has birth as its condition: The knowledge: ‘When there is no birth, there is no aging-and-death: The knowledge: ‘In the past too aging-and-death had birth as its condition: The knowledge: ‘In the past too, had there been no birth, there would have been no aging-and-death: The knowledge: ‘In the future too aging-anddeath will have birth as its condition: The knowledge: ‘In the future too, should there be no birth, there will be no aging-and-death: The knowledge: ‘That knowledge of the stability of the Dhamma is also subject to destruction, vanishing, fading away, and cessation.
“The knowledge: ‘Birth has existence as its condition:... The knowledge: ‘Volitional formations have ignorance as their condition: The knowledge: ‘When there is no ignorance, there are no volitional formations: The knowledge: ‘In the past too volitional formations had ignorance as their condition: The knowledge: ‘In the past too, had there been no ignorance, there would have been no volitional formations: The knowledge: ‘In the future too volitional formations will have ignorance as their condition: The knowledge: ‘In the future too, should there be no ignorance, there will be no volitional formations: The knowledge: ‘That knowledge of the stability of the Dhamma is also subject to destruction, vanishing, fading away, and cessation�.
“These, bhikkhus, are called the seventy-seven cases of knowledge.�
(Samyutta ⲹ, Sutta number 12.34)
Thus, a noble disciple has purified and cleansed the two kinds of knowledge–knowledge of the principle and knowledge of entailment–he is then called a noble disciple who is accomplished in view � one who stands squarely before the door to the Deathless.
Footnotes and references:
[1]:
This analysis of two terms ñṇa and 貹ññ is based on definitions and explanations of PED, 287 & 390 and DB, 127 & 218.
[2]:
BÑ & BB translate Ñṇadassana as ‘knowledge and vision�. And this term can easily be found in AN, SNo. 4.143; and MN, SNo. 2.3; 24.2, 9; 26.18; 29.5; 30.11; 32.7; 77.12; 128.32; and 149.9. According to MA, ñṇadassana also refers to the ‘divine eye�, the ability to see the subtle forms which are invisible to normal vision.
[3]:
The ‘reviewing knowledge� or �retrospective knowledge� (paccavekkhanañṇa) is one of an Arahanta’s characteristics. It is usually shown as the confirmation of his liberation by the phrase “there comes the knowledge: ‘It is liberated�. He understands: ‘Birth is destroyed, the holy life has been lived, what had to be done has been done, there is no more coming to any state of being’� (see MN, SNo. 22.29; MLDB, n. 265).
[4]:
In PED, TRD explains the three standard stages which lead to arahanship or final emancipation as follows: (i) ī-kkhandha ‘code of moral duties�, (ii) -kkhandha ‘code of practice of concentration and meditation�, and (iii) 貹ññ-kkhandha ‘code of intellectual duties or practice of the attainment of highest knowledge� (see PED, 390).
[5]:
Literally, the term means ‘crossed over�. It denotes a ‘completeness�, ‘perfection� or ‘highest state�. Early it consists of the original list of six perfections, later it was eventually increased to ten to complement the ten stages (ū) of a Bodhisattva’s career. It appears these ten ѲԲ Perfections is risen from the ten ī of Early Buddhism. In the later ճ岹 literature such as ٲ첹, ܻṃs or 䲹辱ṭa첹, the word ī comes to signify the perfect virtues that a Bodhisatta must fulfill over many lives to attain Buddhahood. It is for this sense that corresponds to the Sanskrit �� of the ѲԲ literature, even though the numerical lists of virtues overlap only in part (see MLDB, n. 763; and DB, 212).
[6]:
This section is most consulted from the section “The Three Modes of Knowledge� in G.H. Sasaki (1992), Linguistics approach to Buddhist Thought, pp. 90-105.